thumb depicts justice as a goddess equipped with three symbols: a sword symbolizing the court's coercive power; a human scale weighing competing claims in each hand; and a blindfold indicating impartiality. [1]
Justice
is the concept of moral rightness based on ethics, rationality, law, natural law, fairness, religion and/or equity. [2]
|
JUSTICE TICKETS
|
Concept of justice
Justice
concerns the proper ordering of
things and
persons within a
society. As a concept it has been subject to
philosophical,
legal, and
theological reflection and debate throughout our
history. A number of important questions surrounding justice have been fiercely debated over the course of western
history: What is justice? What does it demand of individuals and societies? What is the proper distribution of wealth and resources in society:
equal,
meritocratic,
according to status, or some other arrangement? There are myriad possible answers to these questions from divergent perspectives on the political and philosophical spectrum.
According to most theories of justice, it is overwhelmingly important:
John Rawls, for instance, claims that "Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought."
[3]: Justice can be thought of as distinct from and more fundamental than
benevolence,
charity,
mercy,
generosity or
compassion. Justice has traditionally been associated with concepts of
fate,
reincarnation or
Divine Providence, i.e. with a life in accordance with the cosmic plan. The association of justice with
fairness has thus been historically and culturally rare and is perhaps chiefly a modern innovation.
[4]
Studies at
UCLA in 2008 have indicated that reactions to fairness are "wired" into the brain and that, "Fairness is activating the same part of the brain that responds to food in rats... This is consistent with the notion that being treated fairly satisfies a basic need"
[5]. Research conducted in 2003 at
Emory University,
Georgia, involving Capuchin Monkeys demonstrated that other cooperative animals also possess such a sense and that "
inequality aversion may not be uniquely human."
[6] indicating that ideas of fairness and justice may be instinctual in nature.
Variations of justice
Utilitarianism
is a form of
consequentialism, where punishment is forward-looking. Justified by the ability to achieve future
social benefits resulting in crime reduction, the moral worth of an action is determined by its outcome.
Retributive justice
regulates proportionate response to crime proven by lawful evidence, so that punishment is justly imposed and considered as morally-correct and fully deserved.
The law of
retaliation
(
lex talionis) is a military theory of retributive justice, which says that reciprocity should be equal to the wrong suffered; "life for life, wound for wound, stripe for stripe."
[7]
Restorative justice
is concerned not so much with retribution and punishment as with (a) making the victim whole and (b) reintegrating the offender into society. This approach frequently brings an offender and a victim together, so that the offender can better understand the effect his/her offense had on the victim.
Distributive justice
is directed at the proper allocation of things — wealth, power, reward, respect — between different people.
Oppressive Law
exercises an authoritarian approach to legislation which is "totally unrelated to justice", a tyrannical interpretation of law is one in which the population lives under restriction from unlawful legislation.
Some theorists, such as the classical Greeks and Romans, conceive of justice as a
virtue—a property of people, and only derivatively of their actions and the institutions they create. Others emphasize actions or institutions, and only derivatively the people who bring them about. The source of justice has variously been attributed to
harmony,
divine command,
natural law, or
human creation.
Kinds of justice
thumb
Justice as harmony
In his dialogue
Republic
,
Plato uses Socrates to argue for justice which covers both the just person and the just
City State. Justice is a proper,
harmonious relationship between the warring parts of the person or city. Hence Plato's definition of justice is that justice is the having and doing of what is one's own. A just man is a man in just the right place, doing his best and giving the precise equivalent of what he has received. This applies both at the individual level and at the universal level. A person’s soul has three parts – reason, spirit and desire. Similarly, a city has three parts – Socrates uses the parable of the chariot to illustrate his point: a chariot works as a whole because the two horses’ power is directed by the charioteer. Lovers of wisdom – philosophers, in one sense of the term –
should rule because only they understand what is
good. If one is ill, one goes to a doctor rather than a quack, because the doctor is expert in the subject of health. Similarly, one should trust one’s city to an expert in the subject of the good, not to a mere
politician who tries to gain power by giving people what they want, rather than what’s good for them. Socrates uses the parable of the ship to illustrate this point: the unjust city is like a ship in open ocean, crewed by a powerful but drunken captain (the common people), a group of untrustworthy advisors who try to manipulate the captain into giving them power over the ship’s course (the politicians), and a
navigator (the philosopher) who is the only one who knows how to get the ship to port. For Socrates, the only way the ship will reach its destination – the good – is if the navigator takes charge.
[8]
Justice as divine command
Justice as a divine law is commanding , and indeed the whole of morality, is the authoritative command. Killing is wrong and therefore must be punished and if not punished what should be done? There is a famous paradox called the
Euthyphro dilemma which essentially asks: is something right because God commands it, or does God command it because it's right? If the former, then justice is arbitrary; if the latter, then morality exists on a higher order than God, who becomes little more than a passer-on of moral knowledge. Some Divine command advocates respond by pointing out that the dilemma is false: goodness is the very nature of God and is necessarily expressed in His commands.
Justice as natural law
See also
:
John Locke
Justice as human creation
In contrast to the understandings canvassed so far, justice may be understood as a human
creation
, rather than a
discovery
of harmony, divine command, or natural law. This claim can be understood in a number of ways, with the fundamental division being between those who argue that justice is the creation of
some
humans, and those who argue that it is the creation of
all
humans.
Justice as authoritative command
thumb
According to thinkers including
Thomas Hobbes, justice is created by public, enforceable, authoritative
rules, and injustice is whatever those rules forbid, regardless of their relation to morality. Justice is
created
, not merely described or approximated, by the command of an absolute
sovereign power. This position has some similarities with divine command theory (see above), with the difference that the
state (or other authority) replaces God.
Justice as trickery
In
Republic
, the character
Thrasymachus argues that justice is the interest of the strong—merely a name for what the powerful or cunning ruler has imposed on the people.
Nietzsche, in contrast, argues that justice is part of the slave-morality of the weak many, rooted in their resentment of the strong few, and intended to keep the noble man down. In
Human, All Too Human he states that, "there is no eternal justice."
Justice as mutual agreement
According to thinkers in the social contract tradition, justice is derived from the mutual agreement of everyone concerned; or, in many versions, from what they would agree to under
hypothetical
conditions including equality and absence of bias. This account is considered further below, under ‘Justice as fairness’.
Justice as a subordinate value
According to utilitarian thinkers including
John Stuart Mill, justice is not as fundamental as we often think. Rather, it is derived from the more basic standard of rightness,
consequentialism: what is right is what has the best consequences (usually measured by the total or average
welfare caused). So, the proper principles of justice are those which tend to have the best consequences. These rules may turn out to be familiar ones such as keeping
contracts; but equally, they may not, depending on the facts about real consequences. Either way, what is important is those consequences, and justice is important, if at all, only as derived from that fundamental standard. Mill tries to explain our mistaken belief that justice is overwhelmingly important by arguing that it derives from two natural human tendencies: our desire to retaliate against those who hurt us, and our ability to put ourselves imaginatively in another’s place. So, when we see someone harmed, we project ourselves into her situation and feel a desire to retaliate on her behalf. If this process is the source of our feelings about justice, that ought to undermine our confidence in them.
[9]
Utilitarianism.
Theories of distributive justice
right
Theories of distributive justice need to answer three questions:
#
What goods
are to be distributed? Is it to be
wealth,
power,
respect, some combination of these things?
#
Between what entities
are they to be distributed? Humans (dead, living, future),
sentient beings, the members of a single society,
nations?
# What is the
proper
distribution? Equal,
meritocratic, according to
social status, according to
need, based on property rights and non-aggression?
Distributive justice theorists generally do not answer questions of
who has the right
to enforce a particular favored distribution. On the other hand, property rights theorists argue that there is no "favored distribution." Rather, distribution should be based simply on whatever distribution results from non-coerced interactions or transactions (that is, transactions not based upon force or fraud).
This section describes some widely-held theories of distributive justice, and their attempts to answer these questions.
Egalitarianism
According to the egalitarian, goods should be distributed equally. This basic view can be elaborated in many different ways, according to what goods are to be distributed—wealth, respect, opportunity—and what they are to be distributed equally between—individuals, families, nations, races, species. Commonly-held egalitarian positions include demands for
equality of opportunity and for
equality of outcome.
Giving people what they deserve
In one sense, all theories of distributive justice claim that everyone should get
what they deserve. Theories disagree on the basis for deserts. The main distinction is between theories that argue the basis of just deserts is held equally by everyone, and therefore derive egalitarian accounts of distributive justice—and theories that argue the basis of just deserts is unequally distributed on the basis of, for instance, hard work, and therefore derive accounts of distributive justice by which some should have more than others. This section deals with some popular theories of the second type.
According to
meritocratic
theories, goods, especially wealth and
social status, should be distributed to match individual
merit
, which is usually understood as some combination of talent and hard work. According to
needs
-based theories, goods, especially such basic goods as food, shelter and medical care, should be distributed to meet individuals'
basic needs for them.
Marxism can be regarded as a needs-based theory on some readings of
Marx's slogan "
from each according to his ability, to each according to his need."
[10] According to
contribution
-based theories, goods should be distributed to match an individual's contribution to the overall social good.
Fairness
right at court building in
Olomouc,
Czech Republic
In his
A Theory of Justice
,
John Rawls used a
social contract argument to show that justice, and especially distributive justice, is a form of fairness: an
impartial
distribution of goods. Rawls asks us to imagine ourselves behind a
veil of ignorance
which denies us all knowledge of our personalities, social statuses, moral characters, wealth, talents and life plans, and then asks what theory of justice we would choose to govern our society when the veil is lifted, if we wanted to do the best that we could for ourselves. We don’t know who in particular we are, and therefore can’t bias the decision in our own favour. So, the decision-in-ignorance models fairness, because it excludes selfish
bias. Rawls argues that each of us would reject the
utilitarian theory of justice that we should maximize welfare (see below) because of the risk that we might turn out to be someone whose own good is sacrificed for greater benefits for others. Instead, we would endorse Rawls’s
two principles of justice
:
- Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all.
- Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both
- * to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings principle, and
- * attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity. [11]
This imagined choice justifies these principles as the principles of justice for us, because we would agree to them in a fair decision procedure. Rawls’s theory distinguishes two kinds of goods – (1)
liberties and (2) social and economic goods, i.e. wealth, income and power – and applies different distributions to them – equality between citizens for (1), equality unless inequality improves the position of the worst off for (2).
Property Rights (non-coercion)/Having the right history
Robert Nozick’s influential critique of Rawls argues that distributive justice is not a matter of the whole distribution matching an ideal
pattern
, but of each individual entitlement having the right kind of
history
. It is just that a person has some good (especially, some
property right) if and only if they came to have it by a history made up entirely of events of two kinds:
1. Just acquisition
, especially by working on unowned things; and
2. Just transfer
, that is free gift, sale or other agreement, but not theft (i.e. by force or fraud).
If the chain of events leading up to the person having something meets this criterion, they are entitled to it: that they possess it is just, and what anyone else does or doesn't have or need is irrelevant.
On the basis of this theory of distributive justice, Nozick argues that all attempts to redistribute goods according to an ideal pattern, without the consent of their owners, are theft. In particular,
redistributive taxation is theft.
Some property rights theorists also take a consequentialist view of distributive justice and argue that property rights based justice also has the effect of maximizing the overall wealth of an economic system. They explain that voluntary (non-coerced) transactions always have a property called
pareto efficiency. A pareto efficient transaction is one in which at least one party ends up better off and neither party ends up worse off. The result is that the world is better off in an absolute sense and no one is worse off. Such consequentialist property rights theorists argue that respecting property rights maximizes the number of pareto efficient transactions in the world and minimized the number of non-pareto efficient transactions in the world (i.e. transactions where someone is made worse off). The result is that the world will have generated the greatest total benefit from the limited, scarce resources available in the world. Further, this will have been accomplished without taking anything away from anyone by coercion.
Welfare-maximization
According to the utilitarian, justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals. This may require sacrifice of some for the good of others, so long as everyone’s good is taken impartially into account. Utilitarianism, in general, argues that the standard of justification for actions, institutions, or the whole world, is
impartial welfare consequentialism
, and only indirectly, if at all, to do with
rights,
property,
need, or any other non-utilitarian criterion. These other criteria might be indirectly important, to the extent that human welfare involves them. But even then, such demands as human rights would only be elements in the calculation of overall welfare, not uncrossable barriers to action.
Theories of retributive justice
Theories of retributive justice are concerned with
punishment for wrongdoing, and need to answer three questions:
#
why
punish?
#
who
should be punished?
#
what punishment
should they receive?
This section considers the two major accounts of retributive justice, and their answers to these questions.
Utilitarian
theories look forward to the future consequences of punishment, while
retributive
theories look back to particular acts of wrongdoing, and attempt to balance them with deserved punishment.
Utilitarianism
According to the utilitarian, as already noted, justice requires the maximization of the total or average welfare across all relevant individuals. Punishment is bad treatment of someone, and therefore can’t be good
in itself
, for the utilitarian. But punishment might be a necessary
sacrifice
which maximizes the overall good in the long term, in one or more of three ways:
#
Deterrence
. The credible
threat of punishment might lead people to make different choices; well-designed threats might lead people to make choices which maximize welfare.
#
Rehabilitation
. Punishment might make bad people into better ones. For the utilitarian, all that ‘bad person’ can mean is ‘person who’s likely to cause bad things (like suffering) ’. So, utilitarianism could recommend punishment that changes someone such that they are less likely to cause bad things.
#
Security/Incapacitation
. Perhaps there are people who are irredeemable causers of bad things. If so,
imprisoning them might maximize welfare by limiting their opportunities to cause harm and therefore the benefit lies within protecting society.
So, the reason for punishment is the maximization of welfare, and punishment should be of whomever, and of whatever form and severity, are needed to meet that goal. Worryingly, this may sometimes justify punishing the innocent, or inflicting disproportionately severe punishments, when that will have the best consequences overall (perhaps executing a few suspected
shoplifters live on television would be an effective deterrent to shoplifting, for instance). It also suggests that punishment might turn out
never
to be right, depending on the facts about what actual consequences it has.
[12]
Retributivism
The retributivist will think the utilitarian's argument disastrously mistaken. If someone does something wrong, we must respond to it, and to him or her, as an
individual, not as a part of a calculation of overall welfare. To do otherwise is to disrespect him or her as an individual human being. If the crime had victims, it is to disrespect them, too. Wrongdoing must be balanced or made good in some way, and so the criminal
deserves
to be punished. Retributivism emphasizes retribution – payback – rather than maximization of welfare. Like the theory of distributive justice as giving everyone what they deserve (see above), it links justice with desert. It says that all guilty people, and only guilty people, deserve appropriate punishment. This matches some strong
intuitions about just punishment: that it should be
proportional
to the crime, and that it should be of
only
and
all of
the guilty. However, it is sometimes argued that retributivism is merely
revenge in disguise.
[13] Despite this criticism, there are numerous differences between retribution and revenge: the former is impartial, has a scale of appropriateness and corrects a moral wrong, whereas the latter is personal, unlimited in scale, and often corrects a slight.
Institutions
thumb Supreme Court with President
George W. Bush, October 2005
In a world where people are interconnected but they disagree, institutions are required to instantiate ideals of justice. These institutions may be justified by their approximate instantiation of justice, or they may be deeply unjust when compared with ideal standards — consider the institution of
slavery. Justice is an ideal which the world fails to live up to, sometimes despite good intentions, sometimes disastrously. The question of institutive justice raises issues of
legitimacy,
procedure,
codification and
interpretation, which are considered by legal theorists and by
philosophers of law.
Another definition of justice is an independent investigation of truth.
In a court room, lawyers, the judge and the jury are supposed to be independently investigating the truth of an alleged crime.
In physics, a group of physicists examine data and theoretical concepts to consult on what might be the truth or reality of a phenomenon.
See also
;Other pages
- Criminal justice
- Ethics
- Global justice
- Just war
- Justice (economics)
- Morality
- Social justice
- Teaching for social justice
|
;Justice types
- Commutative justice
- Corrective justice
- Distributive justice
- Restorative justice
- Retributive justice
- Spacial justice
|
References
- Luban, ''Law's Blindfold'', 23
- ''Konow, James. 2003. "Which Is the Fairest One of All? A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories." Journal of Economic Literature 41, no. 4: page 1188''
- John Rawls, ''A Theory of Justice'' (revised edn, Oxford: OUP, 1999), p. 3
- Title Unavailable
- Brain reacts to fairness as it does to money and chocolate, study shows / UCLA Newsroom
- Nature 425, 297-299 (18 September 2003)
- Exodus 21.xxiii-xxv.
- Plato, ''Republic'' trans. Robin Waterfield (Oxford: OUP, 1984).
- John Stuart Mill, ''Utilitarianism'' in ''On Liberty and Other Essays'' ed. John Gray (Oxford: OUP, 1991), Chapter 5.
- Karl Marx, 'Critique of the Gotha Program' in ''Karl Marx: Selected writings'' ed. David McLellan (Oxford: OUP, 1977): 564-70, p. 569.
- John Rawls, ''A Theory of Justice'' (revised edition, Oxford: OUP, 1999), p. 266.
- C. L. Ten, ‘Crime and Punishment’ in Peter Singer ed., ''A Companion to Ethics'' (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993): 366-72.
- Ted Honderich, ''Punishment: The supposed justifications'' (London: Hutchinson & Co., 1969), Chapter 1.